Herbrand universe and Least herbrand Model - prolog

I read the question asked in Herbrand universe, Herbrand Base and Herbrand Model of binary tree (prolog) and the answers given, but I have a slightly different question more like a confirmation and hopefully my confusion will be clarified.
Let P be a program such that we have the following facts and rule:
q(a, g(b)).
q(b, g(b)).
q(X, g(X)) :- q(X, g(g(g(X)))).
From the above program, the Herbrand Universe
Up = {a, b, g(a), g(b), q(a, g(a)), q(a, g(b)), q(b, g(a)), q(b, g(b)), g(g(a)), g(g(b))...e.t.c}
Herbrand base:
Bp = {q(s, t) | s, t E Up}
Now come to my question(forgive me for my ignorance), i included q(a, g(a)) as an element in my Herbrand Universe but from the fact, it states q(a, g(b)). Does that mean that q(a, g(a)) does not suppose to be there?
Also since the Herbrand models are subset of the Herbrand base, how do i determine the least Herbrand model by induction?
Note: I have done a lot of research on this, and some parts are well clear to me but still i have this doubt in me thats why i want to seek the communities opinion. Thank you.

From having the fact q(a,g(b)) you cannot conclude whether or not q(a,g(a)) is in the model. You will have to generate the model first.
For determining the model, start with the facts {q(a,g(b)), q(b,g(b))} and now try to apply your rules to extend it. In your case, however, there is no way to match the right-hand side of the rule q(X,g(X)) :- q(X,g(g(g(X)))). to above facts. Therefore, you are done.
Now imagine the rule
q(a,g(Y)) :- q(b,Y).
This rule could be used to extend our set. In fact, the instance
q(a,g(g(b))) :- q(b,g(b)).
is used: If q(b,g(b)) is present, conclude q(a,g(g(b))). Note that we are using here the rule right-to-left. So we obtain
{q(a,g(b)), q(b,g(b)), q(a,g(g(b)))}
thereby reaching a fixpoint.
Now take as another example you suggested the rule
q(X, g(g(g(X)))) :- q(X, g(X)).
Which permits (I will no longer show the instantiated rule) to generate in one step:
{q(a,g(b)), q(b,g(b)), q(a,g(g(g(b)))), q(b, g(g(g(b))))}
But this is not the end, since, again, the rule can be applied to produce even more! In fact, you have now an infinite model!
{g(a,gn+1(b)), g(b, gn+1(b))}
This right-to-left reading is often very helpful when you are trying to understand recursive rules in Prolog. The top-down reading (left-to-right) is often quite difficult, in particular, since you have to take into account backtracking and general unification.

Concerning your question:
"Also since the Herbrand models are subset of the Herbrand base, how do i determine the least Herbrand model by induction?"
If you have a set P of horn clauses, the definite program, then you can define
a program operator:
T_P(M) := { H S | S is ground substitution, (H :- B) in P and B S in M }
The least model is:
inf(P) := intersect { M | M |= P }
Please note that not all models of a definite program are fixpoints of the
program operator. For example the full herbrand model is always a model of
the program P, which shows that definite programs are always consistent, but
it is not necessarily a fixpoint.
On the other hand each fixpoint of the program operator is a model of the
definite program. Namely if you have T_P(M) = M, then one can conclude
M |= P. So that after some further mathematical reasoning(*) one finds that
the least fixpoint is also the least model:
lfp(T_P) = inf(P)
But we need some further considerations so that we can say that we can determine
the least model by a kind of computation. Namely one easily observes that the
program operator is contiguous, i.e. preserves infinite unions of chains, since
horn clauses do not have forall quantifiers in their body:
union_i T_P(M_i) = T_P(union_i M_i)
So that again after some further mathematical reasoning(*) one finds that we can
compute the least fixpoint via iteration, witch can be used for simple
induction. Every element of the least model has a simple derivation of finite
depth:
union_i T_P^i({}) = lpf(T_P)
Bye
(*)
Most likely you find further hints on the exact mathematical reasoning
needed in this book, but unfortunately I can't recall which sections
are relevant:
Foundations of Logic Programming, John Wylie Lloyd, 1984
http://www.amazon.de/Foundations-Programming-Computation-Artificial-Intelligence/dp/3642968287

Related

Does the Prolog symbol :- mean Implies, Entails or Proves?

In Prolog we can write very simple programs like this:
mammal(dog).
mammal(cat).
animal(X) :- mammal(X).
The last line uses the symbol :- which informally lets us read the final fact as: if X is a mammal then it is also an animal.
I am beginning to learn Prolog and trying to establish which of the following is meant by the symbol :-
Implies (⇒)
Entails (⊨)
Provable (⊢)
In addition, I am not clear on the difference between these three. I am trying to read threads like this one, but the discussion is at a level above my capability, https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/286077/implies-rightarrow-vs-entails-models-vs-provable-vdash.
My thinking:
Prolog works by pattern-matching symbols (unification and search) and so we might be tempted to say the symbol :- means 'syntactic entailment'. However this would only be true of queries that are proven to be true as a result of that syntactic process.
The symbol :- is used to create a database of facts, and therefore is semantic in nature. That means it could be one of Implies (⇒) or Entails (⊨) but I don't know which.
Neither. Or, rather if at all, then it's the implication. The other symbols are above, that is meta-language. The Mathematics Stack Exchange answers explain this quite nicely.
So why :- is not that much of an implication, consider:
p :- p.
In logic, both truth values make this a valid sentence. But in Prolog we stick to the minimal model. So p is false. Prolog uses a subset of predicate logic such that there actually is only one minimal model. And worse, Prolog's actual default execution strategy makes this an infinite loop.
Nevertheless, the most intuitive way to read LHS :- RHS. is to see it as a way to generate new knowledge. Provided RHS is true it follows that also LHS is true. This way one avoids all the paradoxa related to implication.
The direction right-to-left is a bit counter intuitive. This direction is motivated by Prolog's actual execution strategy (which goes left-to-right in this representation).
:- is usually read as if, so something like:
a :- b, c .
reads as
| a is true if b and c are true.
In formal logic, the above would be written as
| a ← b ∧ c
Or
| b and c imply a

Are PROLOG facts bilateral?

So I have just started programming in PROLOG (SWI distribution). I have good logic bases and I am familiar with facts, rules, quantification and all that vocabulary.
As far as I know, you can define a fact such as:
married(a,b).
And I know that if you make a query like:
?: married(X,b).
The answer will be "a". My question is, if I wanted to make a rule that used the fact previously declared, it will consider that "a is married to b", but will it consider that "b is married to a" or do I have to declare another fact like:
married(b,a).
for it to work? Same for any kind of bilateral relationship that can be represented as a fact.
Do you mean if the relation is automatically symmetric? Then no - suppose you have a directed graph with edge(a,b), then you would not want the other direction edge(b,a) to be inferred. Also, what about relations of arity greater than 2?
You can always create the symmetric closure of a predicate as:
r_sym(X,Y) :-
r(X,Y).
r_sym(X,Y) :-
r(Y,X).
Using a new predicate name prevents infinite derivation chains r(X,Y) -> r(Y,X) -> r(X,Y) -> .....

What is the difference between Well-formed formula and a preposition in propositional logic

What is the exact difference between Well-formed formula and a proposition in propositional logic?
There's really not much given about Wff in my book.
My book says: "Propositions are also called sentences or statements. Another term formulae or well-formed formulae also refer to the same. That is, we may also call Well formed formula to refer to a proposition". Does that mean they both are the exact same thing?
Proposition: A statement which is true or false, easy for people to read but hard to manipulate using logical equivalences
WFF: An accurate logical statement which is true or false, there should be an official rigorus definition in your textbook. There are 4 rules they must follow. Harder for humans to read but much more precise and easier to manipulate
Example:
Proposition : All men are mortal
WFF: Let P be the set of people, M(x) denote x is a man and S(x)
denote x is mortal Then for all x in P M(x) -> S(x)
It is most likely that there is a typo in the book. In the quote Propositions are also called sentences or statements. Another term formulae or well-formed formulae also refer to the same. That is, we may also call Well formed formula to refer to a preposition, the word "preposition" should be "proposition".
Proposition :- A statement which is either true or false,but not both.
Propositional Form (necessary to understand Well Formed Formula) :- An assertion which contains at least one propositional variable.
Well Formed Formula :-A propositional form satisfying the following rules and any Wff(Well Formed Formula) can be derived using these rules:-
If P is a propositional variable then it is a wff.
If P is a propositional variable,then ~P is a wff.
If P and Q are two wffs then,(A and B),(A or B),(A implies B),(A is equivalent to B) are all wffs.

Prolog: Coming up with Herbrand Universe and Herbrand Base

I have serious problems to understand the concept of Prolog and the corresponding Herbrand Universe, Herbrand Base and so on.
For example if I have a Prolog program:
p(X,Y) :- q(X,Y), q(Y,X).
s(a).
s(b).
s(c).
q(a,b).
q(b,a).
q(a,c).
I mean - I know what the Prolog program is supposed to do, but I cannot come up with the corresponding Herbrand Universe or Herbrand Base.
For the Herbrand Universe I have to search all variable-free constructor terms.
What are constructors in this context?
I would simply guess that HU = {a,b,c, s(a), s(b), s(c), q(a,a), q(a,b), q(b,a)... p(a,a), p(a,b), ... s(s(a))....}
How to come up with the Herbrand Base?
I'm sorry for all the questions, but I think I'm mixing so many different "Herbrand" things up :-(.
Can anyone help me and explain things to me?
Thank you.
Wikipedia says, "a Herbrand universe ... is defined starting from the set of constants and function symbols in a set of clauses."
So if we follow this definition, here it would consist of atoms a, b, c and compound terms with functors s/1, q/2, p/2 and arguments which are in the Herbrand universe themselves:
hu(a).
hu(b).
hu(c).
hu(s(Y)):- hu(Y).
hu(q(Y,Z)):- hu(Y), hu(Z).
hu(p(Y,Z)):- hu(Y), hu(Z).
"The set of all ground atoms that can be formed from predicate symbols from S and terms from H is called the Herbrand base":
hb(s(Y)):- hu(Y).
hb(q(Y,Z)):- hu(Y), hu(Z).
hb(p(Y,Z)):- hu(Y), hu(Z).

Defining the material conditional in Prolog

I have been trying to acclimate to Prolog and Horn clauses, but the transition from formal logic still feels awkward and forced. I understand there are advantages to having everything in a standard form, but:
What is the best way to define the material conditional operator --> in Prolog, where A --> B succeeds when either A = true and B = true OR B = false? That is, an if->then statement that doesn't fail when if is false without an else.
Also, what exactly are the non-obvious advantages of Horn clauses?
What is the best way to define the material conditional operator --> in Prolog
When A and B are just variables to be bound to the atoms true and false, this is easy:
cond(false, _).
cond(_, true).
But in general, there is no best way because Prolog doesn't offer proper negation, only negation as failure, which is non-monotonic. The closest you can come with actual propositions A and B is often
(\+ A ; B)
which tries to prove A, then goes on to B if A cannot be proven (which does not mean that it is false due to the closed-world assumption).
Negation, however, should be used with care in Prolog.
Also, what exactly are the non-obvious advantages of Horn clauses?
That they have a straightforward procedural reading. Prolog is a programming language, not a theorem prover. It's possible to write programs that have a clear logical meaning, but they're still programs.
To see the difference, consider the classical problem of sorting. If L is a list of numbers without duplicates, then
sort(L, S) :-
permutation(L, S),
sorted(S).
sorted([]).
sorted([_]).
sorted([X,Y|L]) :-
X < Y,
sorted([Y|L]).
is a logical specification of what it means for S to contain the elements of L in sorted order. However, it also has a procedural meaning, which is: try all the permutations of L until you have one that it sorted. This procedure, in the worst case, runs through all n! permutations, even though sorting can be done in O(n lg n) time, making it a very poor sorting program.
See also this question.

Resources